×

LingQをより快適にするためCookieを使用しています。サイトの訪問により同意したと見なされます クッキーポリシー.

image

Crash Course 2: Philosophy., 10a. Aquinas and the Cosmological Arguments. Part 1/2.

10a. Aquinas and the Cosmological Arguments. Part 1/2.

Crash Course Philosophy is brought to you by Squarespace. Squarespace: share your passion with the world.

Nothing gets people talking like proving the existence of God -- just look at the comments on our last video. And that is what Anselm of Canterbury did. He claimed, in the 11th century, to have come up with deductive proof of God's existence, through what we now know as the ontological argument. And, if there was such a thing as a social network of medieval Christian philosophers back then, it was positively abuzz with the news. For a long time. Because, almost 200 years later, Italian theologian and philosopher Thomas Aquinas encountered Anselm's argument. But, like many others, he just didn't buy it. Aquinas did believe in God. It was just that, as a philosopher, he felt that it was important to have evidence for your beliefs. He knew that if he was going to dismiss Anselm's argument, he'd need to come up with something better. So, he set out to construct five arguments that would prove God's existence, once and for all. Yeah, five. Apparently, he was concerned one wasn't going to do it, so he figured that, out of five, one was bound to stick. His first four arguments are known together as the cosmological arguments, as they seek to prove God's existence through what he argued were necessary facts about the universe. So, in keeping with the method that we discussed in our very first episode, we're going to examine these first four arguments of Thomas Aquinas -- and really try to understand them. And then we'll consider their merits… ...and their weaknesses. [Theme Music]

Maybe the most striking thing about the cosmological arguments of Aquinas, at least to modern eyes, is that some of them are firmly based in the natural world. Even though he lived in a pretty unscientific time, Aquinas argued for the existence of God through his understanding of science, and with the help of what he thought was physical evidence.

For example, the first of his cosmological arguments is known as the Argument from Motion. In it, Aquinas observed that we currently live in a world in which things are moving. And he also observed that movement is caused by movers -- things that cause motion. Aquinas was convinced that everything that's moving must have been set into motion by something else that was moving. By this logic, something must have started the motion in the first place.

Otherwise, you'd be stuck in a philosophical quandary known as an infinite regress. You get an infinite regress when, in a chain of reasoning, the evidence for each point along the chain relies on the existence of something that came before it, which in turn relies on something even further back, and so on, with no starting point.

Basically, Aquinas thought the very idea of infinite regress was absurd, logically impossible. Because, it implied that any given series of events began with…nothing. Or, more accurately, never really began. Instead, it could have been going on forever. In the case of physical motion, Aquinas wanted to trace the cause of the movement he saw in the world all the way back to its beginning. And he figured there MUST have been a beginning.

Otherwise, for him, it would be like watching these blocks fall, and being told that nothing ever pushed over the first block. Instead, they had always been falling down forever, backward into eternity. There must have been a time when nothing was in motion, Aquinas thought, and there also must've been a static being that started the motion. And that being, according to Aquinas, is God – the Unmoved Mover.

So his Argument From Motion ran something like this: Objects are in motion Everything in motion was put into motion by something else. There can't be an infinite regress of movers So there must have been a first mover, itself unmoved, and that is God Now, the second cosmological argument of Aquinas was a lot like his first one. Here, he proposed the Argument from Causation, and it, too, sets out to avoid the problem of an infinite regress. But instead of it explaining the motion of objects, it set out to explain causes and effects, in general, all over the universe.

The argument went along these lines: Some things are caused. Anything that's caused has to be caused by something else (since nothing causes itself.) There can't be an infinite regress of causes So there must have been a first causer, itself uncaused, and that is God Just like with the Argument from Motion, the point here is pretty simple: Effects have causes. If you think about how you wound up watching this video, you can trace the line of causation back, from moment to moment. If you think about it long enough, you can probably go pretty far back. But Aquinas said, again: It can't go back forever. There had to be a First Thing that started off the chain of causes and effects. And that Thing is God. Argument number three was the Argument from Contingency. And we should step back and get a little background for this one. In philosophy, we often distinguish between necessary beings and contingent beings. A contingent being is, simply put, any being that could have not existed. That includes you. Sure, you do exist, but you could not have.

If you had never been born, the world would go on. And yes, things would be different – we've all seen It's A Wonderful Life – but the world would go on. Instead, your existence is merely contingent on the existence of other things. In your case, you only exist because a certain sperm met a certain egg and swapped some genetic information. You're basically a fluke. But what does that have to do with God? Well, again, Aquinas believed that there had to be something that prevented an infinite regress of contingency. That would mean that the contingency on which everything existed would just keep going back in time. And we can't have a world where everything is contingent, Aquinas said, because then -- by definition – it all could easily have never existed. So he needed at least one necessary being – a being that has always existed, that always will exist, and that can't not exist, in order to get everything going. And that necessary being is God.

Learn languages from TV shows, movies, news, articles and more! Try LingQ for FREE

10a. Aquinas and the Cosmological Arguments. Part 1/2. 10a. Aquino y los argumentos cosmológicos. Parte 1/2. 10a. 아퀴나스와 우주론적 논증. 1/2부. 10a. Aquinas en de Kosmologische Argumenten. Deel 1/2. 10a. Akwinata i argumenty kosmologiczne. Część 1/2. 10a. Aquino e os Argumentos Cosmológicos. Parte 1/2. 10a. Аквінат і космологічні аргументи. Частина 1/2. 10a. 阿奎那和宇宙论论证。第 1/2 部分。

Crash Course Philosophy is brought to you by Squarespace. Squarespace: share your passion with the world.

Nothing gets people talking like proving the existence of God -- just look at the comments on our last video. And that is what Anselm of Canterbury did. He claimed, in the 11th century, to have come up with deductive proof of God's existence, through what we now know as the ontological argument. And, if there was such a thing as a social network of medieval Christian philosophers back then, it was positively abuzz with the news. Y, si existía entonces algo así como una red social de filósofos cristianos medievales, estaba positivamente alborotada con las noticias. 如果当时有一种中世纪基督教哲学家的社交网络,那么这个消息肯定会引起轰动。 For a long time. 很长一段时间。 Because, almost 200 years later, Italian theologian and philosopher Thomas Aquinas encountered Anselm's argument. 因为接近200年后,意大利神学家和哲学家托马斯·阿奎那遇到了安瑟姆的论点。 But, like many others, he just didn't buy it. Aquinas did believe in God. It was just that, as a philosopher, he felt that it was important to have evidence for your beliefs. He knew that if he was going to dismiss Anselm's argument, he'd need to come up with something better. 他知道如果他要驳斥安瑟姆的论点,他需要想出更好的理由。 So, he set out to construct five arguments that would prove God's existence, once and for all. 因此,他着手构建五个证明上帝存在的论点,一劳永逸。 Yeah, five. 是的,五个。 Apparently, he was concerned one wasn't going to do it, so he figured that, out of five, one was bound to stick. 显然,他担心一个论点不足以证明,所以他认为,在五个中,总会有一个靠谱的。 His first four arguments are known together as the cosmological arguments, as they seek to prove God's existence through what he argued were necessary facts about the universe. So, in keeping with the method that we discussed in our very first episode, we're going to examine these first four arguments of Thomas Aquinas -- and really try to understand them. 因此,为了与我们在第一集中讨论的方法保持一致,我们将审查托马斯·阿奎那的这前四个论点,并试图真正理解它们。 And then we'll consider their merits… ...and their weaknesses. 然后,我们将考虑它们的优点……以及它们的弱点。 [Theme Music] [主题音乐]

Maybe the most striking thing about the cosmological arguments of Aquinas, at least to modern eyes, is that some of them are firmly based in the natural world. 也许Aquinas宇宙论论证最引人注目的一点,至少在现代人看来,就是其中一些蕴含在自然世界中。 Even though he lived in a pretty unscientific time, Aquinas argued for the existence of God through his understanding of science, and with the help of what he thought was physical evidence. 尽管他生活在一个科学较不发达的时代,但Aquinas通过他对科学的理解,以及他认为是物理证据的帮助,为上帝的存在提出了论证。

For example, the first of his cosmological arguments is known as the Argument from Motion. 例如,他的宇宙论论证中的第一个被称为“运动论证”。 In it, Aquinas observed that we currently live in a world in which things are moving. And he also observed that movement is caused by movers -- things that cause motion. Aquinas was convinced that everything that's moving must have been set into motion by something else that was moving. By this logic, something must have started the motion in the first place.

Otherwise, you'd be stuck in a philosophical quandary known as an infinite regress. 否则,你会陷入一种被称为无限回归的哲学困境。 You get an infinite regress when, in a chain of reasoning, the evidence for each point along the chain relies on the existence of something that came before it, which in turn relies on something even further back, and so on, with no starting point. 当推理链中每个点的证据依赖于它之前存在的东西,进而依赖于更进一步的东西,如此循环,没有起点时,你会得到一个无限回归。

Basically, Aquinas thought the very idea of infinite regress was absurd, logically impossible. 基本上,阿奎那认为无限回归的概念是荒谬的,从逻辑上讲不可能。 Because, it implied that any given series of events began with…nothing. 因为这暗示任何一系列事件的开始都是从…无中开始的。 Or, more accurately, never really began. 更准确地说,也许根本就没有开始。 Instead, it could have been going on forever. 相反,它可能一直在持续下去。 In the case of physical motion, Aquinas wanted to trace the cause of the movement he saw in the world all the way back to its beginning. And he figured there MUST have been a beginning.

Otherwise, for him, it would be like watching these blocks fall, and being told that nothing ever pushed over the first block. Instead, they had always been falling down forever, backward into eternity. 相反,它们总是永远地向后倒退,坠入永恒之中。 There must have been a time when nothing was in motion, Aquinas thought, and there also must've been a static being that started the motion. 阿奎那思考时认为,肯定有一个时期没有任何运动,也肯定有一个静止的存在开始了运动。 And that being, according to Aquinas, is God – the Unmoved Mover. 而根据阿奎那的看法,那个存在就是上帝——不动者。

So his Argument From Motion ran something like this: Objects are in motion Everything in motion was put into motion by something else. There can't be an infinite regress of movers So there must have been a first mover, itself unmoved, and that is God Now, the second cosmological argument of Aquinas was a lot like his first one. 无法存在无限的推动者序列,因此必须有第一个推动者,它本身是不被推动的,那就是上帝。现在,阿奎那的第二个宇宙论证与第一个非常相似。 Here, he proposed the Argument from Causation, and it, too, sets out to avoid the problem of an infinite regress. 在这里,他提出了因果论证,它也旨在避免无限回归的问题。 But instead of it explaining the motion of objects, it set out to explain causes and effects, in general, all over the universe. 但与其解释物体的运动不同,它设法解释宇宙中所有地方的原因和效果。

The argument went along these lines: Some things are caused. Anything that's caused has to be caused by something else (since nothing causes itself.) There can't be an infinite regress of causes So there must have been a first causer, itself uncaused, and that is God Just like with the Argument from Motion, the point here is pretty simple: Effects have causes. Il ne peut y avoir une régression infinie des causes. Il doit donc y avoir eu un premier responsable, lui-même sans cause, et c'est Dieu. Tout comme avec l'argument du mouvement, le point ici est assez simple: les effets ont des causes. If you think about how you wound up watching this video, you can trace the line of causation back, from moment to moment. If you think about it long enough, you can probably go pretty far back. But Aquinas said, again: It can't go back forever. There had to be a First Thing that started off the chain of causes and effects. And that Thing is God. Argument number three was the Argument from Contingency. And we should step back and get a little background for this one. In philosophy, we often distinguish between necessary beings and contingent beings. 在哲学中,我们经常区分必然存在和依赖存在。 A contingent being is, simply put, any being that could have not existed. 依赖存在简单来说就是指任何一种本可以不存在的存在。 That includes you. 你也在其中。 Sure, you do exist, but you could not have.

If you had never been born, the world would go on. And yes, things would be different – we've all seen It's A Wonderful Life – but the world would go on. Instead, your existence is merely contingent on the existence of other things. 相反,你的存在仅仅取决于其他事物的存在。 In your case, you only exist because a certain sperm met a certain egg and swapped some genetic information. 就你的情况而言,你之所以存在只是因为某个精子遇见了某个卵子并交换了一些基因信息。 You're basically a fluke. 你基本上是一个偶然。 But what does that have to do with God? Well, again, Aquinas believed that there had to be something that prevented an infinite regress of contingency. 阿奎那认为,必须有某种东西阻止无限的偶然性回归。 That would mean that the contingency on which everything existed would just keep going back in time. Eso significaría que la contingencia sobre la que existía todo seguiría retrocediendo en el tiempo. 这意味着存在一种偶然性,所有事物都会不断地向过去延伸。 And we can't have a world where everything is contingent, Aquinas said, because then -- by definition – it all could easily have never existed. 阿奎那说,我们不能有一个所有事物都是偶然性的世界,因为按照定义,所有事物很容易就不复存在。 So he needed at least one necessary being – a being that has always existed, that always will exist, and that can't not exist, in order to get everything going. And that necessary being is God.