×

We gebruiken cookies om LingQ beter te maken. Als u de website bezoekt, gaat u akkoord met onze cookiebeleid.


image

Crash Course 2: Philosophy., 14b. Anti-Vaxxers, Conspiracy Theories & Epistemic Responsibility. Part 2/2.

14b. Anti-Vaxxers, Conspiracy Theories & Epistemic Responsibility. Part 2/2.

[Video: 05:01]

Now, any amount of rationalization that will convince you that you don't have to study might sound pretty sweet. But, in this case, you're probably going to regret it. Because, after all, if your teacher tells you there's going to be a quiz, chances are, there is going to be a quiz. The fact that you've constructed a brilliant mind game that proves that it won't, isn't going to make that quiz not happen. So, beliefs about vaccines and shipworthiness may be irresponsible because of the danger they pose to others, but this case demonstrates that irresponsible beliefs can be damaging to you, as well. Thanks,Thought Bubble!

Clifford made a pretty convincing case for epistemic responsibility. And it's worth pointing out that his beef wasn't only with ship owners or kids who didn't study. One thing his arguments were meant to show is that religious belief is epistemically irresponsible. Belief in a God whose existence can't be proven was simply “blind faith,” he said. And blind faith leads a person to ignore other facts and arguments, causing them to live an unexamined, unthoughtful life that Clifford described as “one long sin against mankind.”

Unsurprisingly, this idea was met with some counterarguments. Let's hear from one of his interlocutors: 19th century American philosopher and psychologist William James took issue with Clifford's thesis that it is immoral to believe something with insufficient evidence. James acknowledged that one of his beliefs that was most important to him – his belief in God – lacked evidence. So he set out to demonstrate that certain beliefs can be held, morally, even if there's nothing you can really point to, to back them up. Now, James recognized that it would be ridiculous to say it's ok to believe in just anything you wanted. So he narrowed down his claim to argue that, when you adopt a belief, you have options. And the nature of those options can basically determine the moral defensibility of the beliefs you end up holding.

Specifically, he said that the options you face when choosing a belief could be either live or dead;

forced or unforced; And momentous or trivial. You face a live option when you're considering a belief that you could actually see yourself having. For instance, maybe you've never had a pumpkin spice latte. But you love pumpkin, and you love lattes, and you love spice, so you hypothesize that you would enjoy a pumpkin spice latte. That's a live option for you – because you can imagine yourself believing that you'd like a pumpkin spice latte. On the other hand, you probably can't even entertain the possibility that you'd enjoy, like, a dog food spice latte. Try as you might, you just can't imagine accepting that option as an actual belief. So, that's a dead option to you. Now, a forced option is one in which, whatever you do, you've made a choice. You can't not choose. ‘Stay in or go out,' is a good example of a forced option. You have to do one or the other; you can't wait and decide later. Because, as you wait to decide, you've stayed in and thus, you have made your choice. But unforced options are those where you can just opt out of choosing. If I let you pick peanut butter or ham and cheese, you can always just decide to have neither.

So your choice is an unforced option. A momentous option is one that, if you choose it, stands the chance of radically changing your life for the better. Accepting an opportunity to go to the International Space Station, for example, could be momentous. But the option to have French fries with your burger would be trivial – eat them, don't eat them, either way – not gonna make a huge difference in your life. Now, James said that, if you're considering whether to believe something for which there's not sufficient evidence, it's permissible to still believe it – so long as it's a live, forced, and momentous option. And religious belief just happens to fill all of those criteria.

First, James said, believing in God is a live option for himself and a whole lot of other people. He also argued that religious belief is a forced option. That's because he didn't buy the idea that agnosticism was really a thing. He figured that withholding judgment is the same as not believing – so you either believe in God, or you don't. Finally, James thought religious belief is momentous – it has the possibility to greatly improve your life. So, he concluded that we are justified in believing in God in the absence of evidence through faith alone. The problem is, if we're justified in believing in God in the absence of evidence, then we're also justified in believing that it's ok not to vaccinate our kids. Because that, too, is an option that can be described as live, forced, and momentous.

So unfortunately, philosophy can't just make all of the baseless beliefs in the world go away. But it can help you argue against those ideas intelligently. Today we have learned about epistemic responsibility. Clifford says it is always wrong to believe without sufficient evidence, but James says there are some exceptions – namely, religious belief.

Next time we will consider whether we can gamble our way to belief in God – stay tuned!

This episode is brought to you by Squarespace. Squarespace helps to create websites, blogs or online stores for you and for your ideas. Websites look professionally designed regardless of skill level, no coding required.

Try Squarespace at squarespace.com/crashcourse for a special offer. Squarespace: share your passion with the world.

Crash Course Philosophy is produced in association with PBS Digital Studios. You can head over to their channel to check out amazing shows like Brain Craft, PBS Game/Show, and Gross Science.

This episode of Crash Course was filmed in the Doctor Cheryl C. Kinney Crash Course Studio with the help of all of these awesome people and our equally fantastic graphics team is Thought Cafe.

14b. Anti-Vaxxers, Conspiracy Theories & Epistemic Responsibility. Part 2/2. 14b. Anti-Vaxxers, Teorías de la Conspiración y Responsabilidad Epistémica. Parte 2/2. 14b. Anti-Vaxxers, Samenzweringstheorieën & Epistemische Verantwoordelijkheid. Deel 2/2. 14b. Anti-Vaxxers, Teorias da Conspiração e Responsabilidade Epistémica. Parte 2/2. 14b. Антивакцинаторы, теории заговора и эпистемическая ответственность. Часть 2/2. 14b. Anti-Vaxxers, Komplo Teorileri ve Epistemik Sorumluluk. Bölüm 2/2. 14b. Антиваксісти, теорії змови та епістемічна відповідальність. Частина 2/2. 14b. 反疫苗者、阴谋论和认知责任。第 2/2 部分。

[Video: 05:01]

Now, any amount of rationalization that will convince you that you don't have to study might sound pretty sweet. 现在,任何让你相信你不必学习的理性化都可能听起来很甜蜜。 But, in this case, you're probably going to regret it. 但是,在这种情况下,你可能会后悔。 Because, after all, if your teacher tells you there's going to be a quiz, chances are, there is going to be a quiz. 因为毕竟,如果你的老师告诉你会有一个小测验,那很可能就会有一个小测验。 The fact that you've constructed a brilliant mind game that proves that it won't, isn't going to make that quiz not happen. 你构建了一个精彩的心智游戏,证明那个测验不会发生,这并不能让那个测验不发生。 So, beliefs about vaccines and shipworthiness may be irresponsible because of the danger they pose to others, but this case demonstrates that irresponsible beliefs can be damaging to you, as well. 因此,关于疫苗和船只适航性的信念可能是不负责的,因为它们对他人造成的危险,但这个案例表明,不负责任的信念也会对你造成伤害。 Thanks,Thought Bubble! 谢谢,Thought Bubble!

Clifford made a pretty convincing case for epistemic responsibility. And it's worth pointing out that his beef wasn't only with ship owners or kids who didn't study. 值得指出的是,他的抱怨并不仅仅针对船东或不用功学习的孩子。 One thing his arguments were meant to show is that religious belief is epistemically irresponsible. 他的论点之一旨在表明,宗教信仰在认识上是不负责任的。 Belief in a God whose existence can't be proven was simply “blind faith,” he said. 他说,相信一个存在无法证明的上帝只是“盲目信仰”。 And blind faith leads a person to ignore other facts and arguments, causing them to live an unexamined, unthoughtful life that Clifford described as “one long sin against mankind.”

Unsurprisingly, this idea was met with some counterarguments. Let's hear from one of his interlocutors: 19th century American philosopher and psychologist William James took issue with Clifford's thesis that it is immoral to believe something with insufficient evidence. 让我们听听他的谈话者之一:19世纪美国哲学家和心理学家威廉·詹姆斯对克利福德认为凭不足证据相信某事是不道德的观点提出异议。 James acknowledged that one of his beliefs that was most important to him – his belief in God – lacked evidence. 詹姆斯承认,他最看重的信念之一——他对上帝的信仰——缺乏证据支持。 So he set out to demonstrate that certain beliefs can be held, morally, even if there's nothing you can really point to, to back them up. 因此,他着手证明某些信念可以在没有确凿证据支持的情况下,从道德上被持有。 Now, James recognized that it would be ridiculous to say it's ok to believe in just anything you wanted. So he narrowed down his claim to argue that, when you adopt a belief, you have options. 因此,他将他的主张缩小到认为,当你采纳一种信念时,你有选择的权利。 And the nature of those options can basically determine the moral defensibility of the beliefs you end up holding. 这些选择的性质基本上可以决定你最终持有的信念的道德防御性。

Specifically, he said that the options you face when choosing a belief could be either live or dead; 具体而言,他说在选择信仰时面对的选择可能是活的或死的;

forced or unforced; And momentous or trivial. You face a live option when you're considering a belief that you could actually see yourself having. For instance, maybe you've never had a pumpkin spice latte. But you love pumpkin, and you love lattes, and you love spice, so you hypothesize that you would enjoy a pumpkin spice latte. That's a live option for you – because you can imagine yourself believing that you'd like a pumpkin spice latte. On the other hand, you probably can't even entertain the possibility that you'd enjoy, like, a dog food spice latte. 另一方面,你可能无法想象你会喜欢狗粮香料拿铁这种可能性。 Try as you might, you just can't imagine accepting that option as an actual belief. 无论如何,你都无法想象接受那种选项作为真实信仰。 So, that's a dead option to you. 所以对你来说,那是一个行不通的选择。 Now, a forced option is one in which, whatever you do, you've made a choice. 现在,强制选项是这样一种选项:无论你做什么,你都已经做出了选择。 You can't not choose. 你不能不选择。 ‘Stay in or go out,' is a good example of a forced option. “留在家里还是出去”,就是一个很好的强制选项的例子。 You have to do one or the other; you can't wait and decide later. Because, as you wait to decide, you've stayed in and thus, you have made your choice. But unforced options are those where you can just opt out of choosing. 但是非强迫选择是那些你可以选择退出的选择。 If I let you pick peanut butter or ham and cheese, you can always just decide to have neither. 如果我让你选择花生酱或火腿奶酪,你总是可以决定两者都不要。

So your choice is an unforced option. 所以你的选择是一个非强迫选择。 A momentous option is one that, if you choose it, stands the chance of radically changing your life for the better. 重大的选择是指,如果你选择它,就有可能彻底改变你的生活变得更好。 Accepting an opportunity to go to the International Space Station, for example, could be momentous. 比如,接受去国际空间站的机会可能是重大的。 But the option to have French fries with your burger would be trivial – eat them, don't eat them, either way – not gonna make a huge difference in your life. 但选择在汉堡包里加薯条就是琐碎的—吃或者不吃都无所谓—这不会对你的生活产生很大影响。 Now, James said that, if you're considering whether to believe something for which there's not sufficient evidence, it's permissible to still believe it – so long as it's a live, forced, and momentous option. 詹姆斯说,如果你在考虑是否相信一个没有充分证据支持的东西,只要这个选择是存在的、强制的和重要的,那么仍然相信它是可以接受的。 And religious belief just happens to fill all of those criteria. 而宗教信仰恰好符合所有这些标准。

First, James said, believing in God is a live option for himself and a whole lot of other people. 首先,詹姆斯说,对上帝的信仰对他本人和许多其他人来说是一个有意义的选择。 He also argued that religious belief is a forced option. 他还主张宗教信仰是一种被迫选择。 That's because he didn't buy the idea that agnosticism was really a thing. 这是因为他不相信不可知论真的存在。 He figured that withholding judgment is the same as not believing – so you either believe in God, or you don't. 他认为暂不作出判断等同于不信仰 - 所以你要么相信上帝,要么不相信。 Finally, James thought religious belief is momentous – it has the possibility to greatly improve your life. So, he concluded that we are justified in believing in God in the absence of evidence through faith alone. 因此,他得出结论说,我们在没有证据的情况下通过信仰就能证明相信上帝是正当的。 The problem is, if we're justified in believing in God in the absence of evidence, then we're also justified in believing that it's ok not to vaccinate our kids. 问题在于,如果我们在没有证据的情况下相信上帝是正当的,那么我们也可以认为不给孩子接种疫苗也是正当的。 Because that, too, is an option that can be described as live, forced, and momentous. 因为那也是一个可以被描述为重要、迫切和重大的选择。

So unfortunately, philosophy can't just make all of the baseless beliefs in the world go away. But it can help you argue against those ideas intelligently. Today we have learned about epistemic responsibility. Clifford says it is always wrong to believe without sufficient evidence, but James says there are some exceptions – namely, religious belief.

Next time we will consider whether we can gamble our way to belief in God – stay tuned! 下次我们会考虑我们是否能通过赌博的方式相信上帝 - 敬请关注!

This episode is brought to you by Squarespace. 本集由Squarespace赞助。 Squarespace helps to create websites, blogs or online stores for you and for your ideas. Squarespace帮助您为自己和自己的想法创建网站、博客或在线商店。 Websites look professionally designed regardless of skill level, no coding required.

Try Squarespace at squarespace.com/crashcourse for a special offer. Squarespace: share your passion with the world.

Crash Course Philosophy is produced in association with PBS Digital Studios. You can head over to their channel to check out amazing shows like Brain Craft, PBS Game/Show, and Gross Science. 您可以前往他们的频道查看像Brain Craft、PBS Game/Show和Gross Science这样的精彩节目。

This episode of Crash Course was filmed in the Doctor Cheryl C. Kinney Crash Course Studio with the help of all of these awesome people and our equally fantastic graphics team is Thought Cafe. 这一集Crash Course是在 Doctor Cheryl C. Kinney Crash Course Studio 拍摄的,得到了所有这些了不起的人和我们同样出色的图形团队 Thought Cafe 的帮助。