×

LingQ'yu daha iyi hale getirmek için çerezleri kullanıyoruz. Siteyi ziyaret ederek, bunu kabul edersiniz: çerez politikası.

image

Crash Course 2: Philosophy., 03b. How to Argue - Induction & Abduction. Part 2/2.

03b. How to Argue - Induction & Abduction. Part 2/2.

Abduction doesn't reason straight from a premise to a conclusion, as we've seen in deduction and induction. Instead, it reasons by ruling out possible explanations until you're left with the most plausible one, given the evidence. Consider this:

Anna told you she failed her physics midterm.

Anna hasn't been in physics class since your teacher graded the exams. Anna has been in sociology class, which meets right after physics.

Anna dropped physics.

Now, with only these premises, we can't deductively or inductively prove our conclusion – that she dropped physics. But, it's a justifiable conclusion, because, given what we know, dropping the class is the most plausible explanation of events. We know she's not sick – because she's still going to sociology – and we know she had good reason to withdraw from the class, because she was unlikely to pass. Concluding that she dropped the course makes the most tidy use of our information, without leaving any loose ends. So let's look at another one: You and your roommate ate sushi last night.

You both wake up with violent stomachaches.

You and your roommate ate some bad sushi.

The mere fact that you're both sick doesn't prove that the sushi caused the sickness. But, given that you both ate the same thing and you both have the same symptoms – absent other information, like that a stomach virus is going around your dorm – the best explanation is that the sushi caused your intestinal anguish.

Now, like induction, abduction doesn't give us certainty. But it is a really useful way to get through puzzling situations when you don't have clear evidence from the past to help you out. Doctors use abduction a lot when they're diagnosing illnesses, and detectives of course use it when piecing together evidence. You probably use it pretty often too – just beware, because abduction must be used carefully! It uses only information you have at hand -- that's why doctors and detectives work so hard to dig up more data, and re-create events from the past, so they can help draw better conclusions. All right, now that we've looked at some argument types, let's find out how philosophers use arguments to interact with each other. Because, philosophers don't argue like other people do. It's not like the conversation you have around the dinner table about whether the Patriots are better than the Seahawks, or why plain M&Ms are superior to peanut, which is clearly a preposterous position to take. Philosophers hold each other to different, higher standards. They don't teach each other get away with saying, “I reject your argument because I don't like its conclusion.” Or, “That's preposterous, peanut M&Ms are so good.” Instead, if you disagree with a conclusion, you need to give reasons, just like the first person did when they made their case. Both people involved in this kind of exchange are known as interlocutors, because we have to name everything. The first one advances an argument, and the second one can either accept it, or offer a counterargument, which is just what it sounds like – an argument offered in opposition to another argument.

Think back to Socrates and the beard. You think Socrates had a beard, and your reasoning is that most men in his time and place had them. I, however, think you're wrong. So I give you a counterargument.

Gorgias, a contemporary of Socrates, said Socrates couldn't grow a beard and that he would sneak into barbershops and steal discarded clippings to fashion fake beards for himself. Therefore, Socrates didn't have a (real) beard. And I just want to point out that this is an actual philosophy conspiracy theory.

Gorgias was a real guy, who differed with Socrates on many things, and the dispute was said to have gotten personal.

According to accounts of the time, Gorgias actually spread the rumor that Socrates wore, like, a beard-wig, in an effort to shame and discredit his rival. I mean, how could you be a good thinker if you weren't a good beard-grower. Gorgias' gossip didn't go over well with everyone, and in this instance, let's say you are skeptical about it too. So you counter my counterargument with a counter-counterargument. Gorgias was known for being a gossip, and for hating Socrates, and trying to make him look bad. His fake beard tale seems wildly unlikely. Therefore, we can't take Gorgias' statement seriously, so we should fall back on the best information we have, which is that most of the men in his time and place had beards. And as you can see, arguments of different styles can be used in the same exchange.

Like, the original argument, about Socrates probably having a beard, was inductive. But this last counterargument is abductive. And that's fine. Arguments are meant to be useful, so we don't have to use the same kind of reasoning when we argue. This way of exchanging ideas through dialogue was popularized by Socrates, and so has become known as the Socratic method. Socrates thought dialogue was the best way to learn, and to get at truth. And it's important to note that, while philosophers have a reputation for being an argumentative lot, they don't think of the Socratic method as something that results in a winner and a loser. Rather, it's an exercise that brings both interlocutors closer to the truth. The goal of the philosopher is not to win, but to find truth, so you shouldn't be disappointed if someone presents a counterargument that you can't find a response to. When that happens, a good philosopher will be grateful to their interlocutor for helping them reject false beliefs and build stronger ones.

Today you learned about two more types of philosophical reasoning, induction and abduction. You've seen their strengths, and their weaknesses. And you've also learned about counterarguments, and the Socratic method. This episode is brought to you by Squarespace. Squarespace helps to create websites, blogs or online stores for you and your ideas. Websites look professionally designed regardless of skill level, no coding required. Try Squarespace at squarespace.com/crashcourse for a special offer.

Crash Course Philosophy is produced in association with PBS Digital Studios. You can head over to their channel to check out amazing shows like BrainCraft. It's OK To Be Smart, and PBS Idea Channel. This episode was filmed in the Doctor Cheryl C. Kinney Crash Course Studio with the help of these amazing people and our Graphics Team is Thought Cafe.

Learn languages from TV shows, movies, news, articles and more! Try LingQ for FREE

03b. How to Argue - Induction & Abduction. Part 2/2. 03b. Wie man argumentiert - Induktion und Abduktion. Teil 2/2. 03b. Cómo argumentar - Inducción y abducción. Parte 2/2. 03b. Hoe te argumenteren - Inductie & Abductie. Deel 2/2. 03b. Jak argumentować - indukcja i uprowadzenie. Część 2/2. 03b. Como Argumentar - Indução e Abdução. Parte 2/2. 03b. Как спорить - индукция и абдукция. Часть 2/2. 03b. Як сперечатися - індукція та абдукція. Частина 2/2. 03b. 如何辩论 - 归纳推理与溯因推理。第 2/2 部分。

Abduction doesn't reason straight from a premise to a conclusion, as we've seen in deduction and induction. 正如我们在演绎和归纳中看到的那样,溯因推理并不是直接从前提推理到结论。 Instead, it reasons by ruling out possible explanations until you're left with the most plausible one, given the evidence. Вместо этого он рассуждает, исключая возможные объяснения, пока не останется наиболее правдоподобное из них с учетом имеющихся данных. Consider this:

Anna told you she failed her physics midterm.

Anna hasn't been in physics class since your teacher graded the exams. Anna has been in sociology class, which meets right after physics. 安娜上的是社会学课,这门课紧接在物理课之后。

Anna dropped physics.

Now, with only these premises, we can't deductively or inductively prove our conclusion – that she dropped physics. 现在,仅凭这些前提,我们无法通过演绎或归纳来证明我们的结论——她放弃了物理学。 But, it's a justifiable conclusion, because, given what we know, dropping the class is the most plausible explanation of events. We know she's not sick – because she's still going to sociology – and we know she had good reason to withdraw from the class, because she was unlikely to pass. Concluding that she dropped the course makes the most tidy use of our information, without leaving any loose ends. So let's look at another one: 我们再看看另一个: You and your roommate ate sushi last night.

You both wake up with violent stomachaches.

You and your roommate ate some bad sushi.

The mere fact that you're both sick doesn't prove that the sushi caused the sickness. But, given that you both ate the same thing and you both have the same symptoms – absent other information, like that a stomach virus is going around your dorm – the best explanation is that the sushi caused your intestinal anguish. 但是,考虑到你们吃了同样的东西,并且都有同样的症状——没有其他信息,比如胃病毒正在你们的宿舍里传播——最好的解释就是寿司导致了你的肠胃疼痛。

Now, like induction, abduction doesn't give us certainty. 现在,像归纳推理一样,溯因推理并不能给我们确定性。 But it is a really useful way to get through puzzling situations when you don't have clear evidence from the past to help you out. Doctors use abduction a lot when they're diagnosing illnesses, and detectives of course use it when piecing together evidence. You probably use it pretty often too – just beware, because abduction must be used carefully! It uses only information you have at hand -- that's why doctors and detectives work so hard to dig up more data, and re-create events from the past, so they can help draw better conclusions. All right, now that we've looked at some argument types, let's find out how philosophers use arguments to interact with each other. 好了,现在我们已经了解了一些论证类型,让我们来看看哲学家们如何使用论证来相互交流。 Because, philosophers don't argue like other people do. It's not like the conversation you have around the dinner table about whether the Patriots are better than the Seahawks, or why plain M&Ms are superior to peanut, which is clearly a preposterous position to take. 这不像你在餐桌上讨论爱国者队是否比海鹰队更好,或者为什么普通的 M&M 巧克力豆比花生更好,这显然是一个荒谬的立场。 Philosophers hold each other to different, higher standards. They don't teach each other get away with saying, “I reject your argument because I don't like its conclusion.” Or, “That's preposterous, peanut M&Ms are so good.” No se enseñan a decir: "Rechazo tu argumento porque no me gusta su conclusión", o: "Eso es absurdo, los M&M de cacahuete están buenísimos". Instead, if you disagree with a conclusion, you need to give reasons, just like the first person did when they made their case. En cambio, si no estás de acuerdo con una conclusión, tienes que dar razones, igual que hizo la primera persona cuando expuso sus argumentos. Both people involved in this kind of exchange are known as interlocutors, because we have to name everything. Las dos personas que participan en este tipo de intercambio se denominan interlocutores, porque hay que nombrarlo todo. The first one advances an argument, and the second one can either accept it, or offer a counterargument, which is just what it sounds like – an argument offered in opposition to another argument.

Think back to Socrates and the beard. 回想一下苏格拉底和胡须。 You think Socrates had a beard, and your reasoning is that most men in his time and place had them. I, however, think you're wrong. 然而,我认为你错了。 So I give you a counterargument.

Gorgias, a contemporary of Socrates, said Socrates couldn't grow a beard and that he would sneak into barbershops and steal discarded clippings to fashion fake beards for himself. Therefore, Socrates didn't have a (real) beard. And I just want to point out that this is an actual philosophy conspiracy theory. 我只想指出,这是一个真正的哲学阴谋论。

Gorgias was a real guy, who differed with Socrates on many things, and the dispute was said to have gotten personal. 高尔吉亚是一个真实存在的人,他在很多事情上与苏格拉底意见相左,而且据说这场争论已经发展到个人问题。

According to accounts of the time, Gorgias actually spread the rumor that Socrates wore, like, a beard-wig, in an effort to shame and discredit his rival. I mean, how could you be a good thinker if you weren't a good beard-grower. Gorgias' gossip didn't go over well with everyone, and in this instance, let's say you are skeptical about it too. So you counter my counterargument with a counter-counterargument. 所以你用反驳的论点来反驳我的反驳论点。 Gorgias was known for being a gossip, and for hating Socrates, and trying to make him look bad. His fake beard tale seems wildly unlikely. Therefore, we can't take Gorgias' statement seriously, so we should fall back on the best information we have, which is that most of the men in his time and place had beards. And as you can see, arguments of different styles can be used in the same exchange.

Like, the original argument, about Socrates probably having a beard, was inductive. 就像,关于苏格拉底可能留着胡子的原始论点是归纳的。 But this last counterargument is abductive. And that's fine. Arguments are meant to be useful, so we don't have to use the same kind of reasoning when we argue. This way of exchanging ideas through dialogue was popularized by Socrates, and so has become known as the Socratic method. 这种通过对话来交流思想的方式由苏格拉底推广,因此被称为苏格拉底式方法。 Socrates thought dialogue was the best way to learn, and to get at truth. And it's important to note that, while philosophers have a reputation for being an argumentative lot, they don't think of the Socratic method as something that results in a winner and a loser. 值得注意的是,尽管哲学家们以喜欢争论而闻名,但他们并不认为苏格拉底式的辩论方法会导致胜利者和失败者。 Rather, it's an exercise that brings both interlocutors closer to the truth. The goal of the philosopher is not to win, but to find truth, so you shouldn't be disappointed if someone presents a counterargument that you can't find a response to. When that happens, a good philosopher will be grateful to their interlocutor for helping them reject false beliefs and build stronger ones.

Today you learned about two more types of philosophical reasoning, induction and abduction. You've seen their strengths, and their weaknesses. And you've also learned about counterarguments, and the Socratic method. This episode is brought to you by Squarespace. Squarespace helps to create websites, blogs or online stores for you and your ideas. Websites look professionally designed regardless of skill level, no coding required. Try Squarespace at squarespace.com/crashcourse for a special offer.

Crash Course Philosophy is produced in association with PBS Digital Studios. You can head over to their channel to check out amazing shows like BrainCraft. It's OK To Be Smart, and PBS Idea Channel. This episode was filmed in the Doctor Cheryl C. Kinney Crash Course Studio with the help of these amazing people and our Graphics Team is Thought Cafe.