×

LingQ'yu daha iyi hale getirmek için çerezleri kullanıyoruz. Siteyi ziyaret ederek, bunu kabul edersiniz: çerez politikası.

image

Crash Course 2: Philosophy., 10b. Aquinas and the Cosmological Arguments. Part 1/2.

10b. Aquinas and the Cosmological Arguments. Part 1/2.

{5:12}

Aquinas spelled out the reasoning of his Argument from Contingency this way: there are contingent things Contingent things can cause other contingent things, but there can't only be contingent things Because that would mean that there's an infinite regress of contingency, and a possibility that nothing might have existed An infinite regress is impossible. So there must be at least one necessary thing, and that is God Let that marinate in your brain for a minute while unpack the next argument.

This one is built on the idea that we simply need a measuring stick in order to understand the value of things. Good/bad, big/small, hot/cold – none of these concepts can exist in isolation. If you go out for a walk and you see an animal, and it's like this big, that animal would be on the small side if it turned out to be a dog. But if it were a rat, that would be HUGE.

How do we know? Because we gauge the size of things in terms of other things. The same idea applies to more abstract concepts, like your grades. How do we know that an A is good? Because it's at the top -- we know that there are grades lower than an A, but nothing higher. And Aquinas thought that all of our value concepts would just be floating randomly in space if there weren't some anchor – something that defined the value of everything else, by being perfect – and that, again, is God. This is how Aquinas developed Number four, known as Argument from Degrees. Properties come in degrees In order for there to be degrees of perfection, there must be something perfect against which everything else is measured God is the pinnacle of perfection Ok, so we've considered Aquinas' four cosmological arguments. But remember, that's only step one. The next, and equally important step in philosophy, is critical evaluation. So what do we make of ‘em? As philosophers, if you think an argument is flawed, it's your job to try and figure out why. And by and large, philosophers – theists and atheists alike – have been relatively unimpressed by these four, having found many problems in them.

For one thing, these arguments don't seem to establish the existence of any particular god. Even if the arguments are correct, it doesn't look like Aquinas gets us to the personal, loving God that many people pray to. Instead, we're left with unmoved movers and uncaused causers who seem to have little in common with the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob ... the God who feels emotions, and cares about his creation, and answers prayers. Basically, this objection says that Aquinas' god is so far removed from the god that theists actually believe in, that it doesn't help anything. But maybe you're happy just believing someone's out there. That's fine. But then how about multiple someones? Because – guess what – Aquinas' arguments don't rule out polytheism. There's nothing in any of his arguments to prove that God isn't actually, like, a committee. Aquinas' cosmological arguments also don't prove the existence of a sentient God. So, it might be an old guy with a beard. It might be six old guys with beards. But it also might be an egg, or a turtle, or just a big block of stone.

These observations have made some philosophers uncomfortable with Aquinas' ultimate conclusion. But there are two objections that are thought by some to be real nails in its coffin. The first is simply that Aquinas was wrong in his insistence that there can't be an infinite regress of anything. Aquinas takes it as a given that there had to be a starting point for everything -- whether it's the movement of objects, or causes and effects, or contingent beings being created. But it's unclear that this is true, or why it has to be true. If infinite regress can be possible, then Aquinas' first two arguments fall apart. But perhaps the most significant charge made against Aquinas' arguments is that they're self-defeating -- that is, they actually prove themselves wrong. For example: If Aquinas is right that everything must have been put in motion by something else, and everything must have a cause other than itself, then it seems that God should be subject to those same stipulations. And if God is somehow exempt from those rules, then why couldn't other things be exempt from them too? If they can exist without God being responsible them, then we don't need God to establish things in the first place. All right, I've given you a lot to think about. So before we close, let's pause and remind ourselves about a couple of things. First, you can accept a conclusion but reject an argument. So you might agree with Aquinas that God exists, but think none of his arguments prove it.

Second, if you disagree with an argument, you don't get to just say, “yeah, you're wrong.” You have to give a counterargument. What did Aquinas get wrong, and how can you do better? Why are your reasons superior to his? Remember, philosophy is a dialectic.

Yes, Aquinas has been dead for centuries. But he started a conversation. And you get to participate in that when you engage with his arguments, and offer your own, either in an effort to help him out – by fixing flaws in his arguments while preserving his conclusion – or by refuting his entire project.

This is what it means to do philosophy – to engage with arguments about stuff that matters. And whether or not there's a God seems to matter quite a bit, particularly in the lives of theists. Today we've learned about cosmological arguments, and considered four of them. Next time, we'll look at Aquinas' fifth argument, the teleological argument. This episode of Crash Course Philosophy is made possible by Squarespace. Squarespace is a way to create a website, blog or online store for you and your ideas. Squarespace features a user-friendly interface, custom templates and 24/7 customer support. Try Squarespace at squarespace.com/crashcourse for a special offer.

Crash Course Philosophy is produced in association with PBS Digital Studios. You can head over to their channel and check out some amazing shows like PBS Idea Channel, The Chatterbox, and PBS Space Time.

This episode of Crash Course was filmed in the Doctor Cheryl C. Kinney Crash Course Studio with the help of all these awesome people and our equally fantastic graphics team is Thought Cafe.

Learn languages from TV shows, movies, news, articles and more! Try LingQ for FREE

10b. Aquinas and the Cosmological Arguments. Part 1/2. 10b. Aquin und die kosmologischen Argumente. Teil 1/2. 10b.アクィナスと宇宙論的議論。パート1/2。 10b. 아퀴나스와 우주론적 논증. 1/2부. 10b. Aquinas en de Kosmologische Argumenten. Deel 1/2. 10b. Akwinata i argumenty kosmologiczne. Część 1/2. 10b. Aquino e os Argumentos Cosmológicos. Parte 1/2. 10b. Аквинат и космологические аргументы. Часть 1/2. 10b. Аквінат і космологічні аргументи. Частина 1/2.

{5:12}

Aquinas spelled out the reasoning of his Argument from Contingency this way: there are contingent things Contingent things can cause other contingent things, but there can't only be contingent things Because that would mean that there's an infinite regress of contingency, and a possibility that nothing might have existed An infinite regress is impossible. ||||||||||||||||||||||contingent entities||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||| 阿奎那这样阐述了他的「虚无可能性论证」的推理:有有条件的事物。有条件的事物可以导致其他有条件的事物,但不能只有有条件的事物,因为那将意味着存在无限的虚无可能性,以及没有任何东西可能存在的可能性。无限的虚无可能性是不可能的。 So there must be at least one necessary thing, and that is God Let that marinate in your brain for a minute while unpack the next argument. |||||||||||||||mariner||||||||||| 因此,必须至少存在一件必然的事物,那就是上帝。在您的脑海中沉思片刻,然后再解开下一个论证。

This one is built on the idea that we simply need a measuring stick in order to understand the value of things. 这个论证是建立在我们需要一个度量标准来了解事物价值的想法上。 Good/bad, big/small, hot/cold – none of these concepts can exist in isolation. If you go out for a walk and you see an animal, and it's like this big, that animal would be on the small side if it turned out to be a dog. 如果你出去散步,看到一个动物,大概是这么大,如果它是一只狗的话,那个动物算是比较小的。 But if it were a rat, that would be HUGE. 但如果是只老鼠的话,那就太大了。

How do we know? 我们怎么知道呢? Because we gauge the size of things in terms of other things. The same idea applies to more abstract concepts, like your grades. How do we know that an A is good? Because it's at the top -- we know that there are grades lower than an A, but nothing higher. And Aquinas thought that all of our value concepts would just be floating randomly in space if there weren't some anchor – something that defined the value of everything else, by being perfect – and that, again, is God. 阿奎那思想认为,如果没有一些锚点-即定义其他一切价值的东西-一切价值概念将随机漂浮在空间中,而这个锚点就是完美的上帝。 This is how Aquinas developed Number four, known as Argument from Degrees. 这就是阿奎那发展出的第四个观点,称为程度论证。 Properties come in degrees In order for there to be degrees of perfection, there must be something perfect against which everything else is measured God is the pinnacle of perfection Ok, so we've considered Aquinas' four cosmological arguments. 属性有程度为了有完美的程度,必须有一些完美的东西,以此来衡量其他一切事物,上帝是完美的顶点。好的,我们已经考虑过阿奎那的四个宇宙论证。 But remember, that's only step one. The next, and equally important step in philosophy, is critical evaluation. So what do we make of ‘em? As philosophers, if you think an argument is flawed, it's your job to try and figure out why. 作为哲学家,如果你认为一个论点有缺陷,你的工作就是努力找出为什么。 And by and large, philosophers – theists and atheists alike – have been relatively unimpressed by these four, having found many problems in them. 而且总的来说,哲学家——无论是有神论者还是无神论者——对这四个论点并不十分满意,因为他们发现其中有许多问题。

For one thing, these arguments don't seem to establish the existence of any particular god. 首先,这些论点似乎并没有证明任何特定神的存在。 Even if the arguments are correct, it doesn't look like Aquinas gets us to the personal, loving God that many people pray to. 即使论点正确,看起来阿奎那也没有让我们接近许多人祈祷的个人、充满爱的上帝。 Instead, we're left with unmoved movers and uncaused causers who seem to have little in common with the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob ... the God who feels emotions, and cares about his creation, and answers prayers. 相反,我们只剩下静止的动力和无因的原因,它们似乎与亚伯拉罕、以撒和雅各的上帝没有什么共同之处……即感受情绪、关心他的创造物并回应祈祷的上帝。 Basically, this objection says that Aquinas' god is so far removed from the god that theists actually believe in, that it doesn't help anything. 基本上,这个反对意见表明阿奎那的上帝与有神论者实际相信的上帝相去甚远,对于任何事物都没有帮助。 But maybe you're happy just believing someone's out there. 也许你只是乐意相信有人在那里。 That's fine. 那也没问题。 But then how about multiple someones? 但是怎么样考虑多个人呢? Because – guess what – Aquinas' arguments don't rule out polytheism. There's nothing in any of his arguments to prove that God isn't actually, like, a committee. 他的任何论点都没有证明上帝实际上不像一个委员会。 Aquinas' cosmological arguments also don't prove the existence of a sentient God. 阿奎那的宇宙论证也不能证明存在一个有感情的上帝。 So, it might be an old guy with a beard. 所以,可能是一个有胡须的老人。 It might be six old guys with beards. But it also might be an egg, or a turtle, or just a big block of stone.

These observations have made some philosophers uncomfortable with Aquinas' ultimate conclusion. But there are two objections that are thought by some to be real nails in its coffin. |||||||||||||clous||| Pero hay dos objeciones que algunos consideran verdaderos clavos en su ataúd. 但有两个反对意见被一些人认为是其真正致命伤。 The first is simply that Aquinas was wrong in his insistence that there can't be an infinite regress of anything. 首先是有人认为只是因为阿奎那坚持认为不能存在任何无限回归而错了。 Aquinas takes it as a given that there had to be a starting point for everything -- whether it's the movement of objects, or causes and effects, or contingent beings being created. 阿奎那认为一切必须有一个起点 -- 无论是物体的运动,还是原因和效果,或者有条件的存在被创造。 But it's unclear that this is true, or why it has to be true. If infinite regress can be possible, then Aquinas' first two arguments fall apart. 如果无限回归是可能的,那么阿奎那的前两个论点就会崩溃。 But perhaps the most significant charge made against Aquinas' arguments is that they're self-defeating -- that is, they actually prove themselves wrong. 但也许针对阿奎那论证最重要的指控是,它们是自相矛盾的 - 也就是说,它们实际上证明了自己是错误的。 For example: If Aquinas is right that everything must have been put in motion by something else, and everything must have a cause other than itself, then it seems that God should be subject to those same stipulations. |||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||stipulations 例如:如果阿奎那正确认为一切都必须由其他事物推动,并且一切都必须有自身以外的原因,那么似乎上帝也应该受到相同规定的约束。 And if God is somehow exempt from those rules, then why couldn't other things be exempt from them too? 如果上帝在某种程度上不受这些规则约束,那么其他事物为什么不能免除这些规则呢? If they can exist without God being responsible them, then we don't need God to establish things in the first place. 如果它们可以在没有上帝负责的情况下存在,那么我们就不需要上帝来建立事物。 All right, I've given you a lot to think about. 好的,我已经给了你很多东西去思考。 So before we close, let's pause and remind ourselves about a couple of things. First, you can accept a conclusion but reject an argument. So you might agree with Aquinas that God exists, but think none of his arguments prove it.

Second, if you disagree with an argument, you don't get to just say, “yeah, you're wrong.” You have to give a counterargument. 其次,如果你不同意一个论点,你不能只是说:“是的,你错了。”你必须提出一个对立的论点。 What did Aquinas get wrong, and how can you do better? 阿奎那错在哪里,你能做得更好吗? Why are your reasons superior to his? 为什么你的理由比他的更优越? Remember, philosophy is a dialectic. Onthoud dat filosofie een dialectiek is. 记住,哲学是一种辩证法。

Yes, Aquinas has been dead for centuries. 是的,阿奎那已经死了几个世纪了。 But he started a conversation. 但他开始了一场对话。 And you get to participate in that when you engage with his arguments, and offer your own, either in an effort to help him out – by fixing flaws in his arguments while preserving his conclusion – or by refuting his entire project.

This is what it means to do philosophy – to engage with arguments about stuff that matters. And whether or not there's a God seems to matter quite a bit, particularly in the lives of theists. Today we've learned about cosmological arguments, and considered four of them. Next time, we'll look at Aquinas' fifth argument, the teleological argument. This episode of Crash Course Philosophy is made possible by Squarespace. Squarespace is a way to create a website, blog or online store for you and your ideas. Squarespace features a user-friendly interface, custom templates and 24/7 customer support. Try Squarespace at squarespace.com/crashcourse for a special offer.

Crash Course Philosophy is produced in association with PBS Digital Studios. You can head over to their channel and check out some amazing shows like PBS Idea Channel, The Chatterbox, and PBS Space Time.

This episode of Crash Course was filmed in the Doctor Cheryl C. Kinney Crash Course Studio with the help of all these awesome people and our equally fantastic graphics team is Thought Cafe.